(Part 10) Heidegger’s Reading of Hölderlin’s Poem “The Ister”
I’ve been working to uncover the tragic insight into the human condition that Heidegger finds in Sophocles’ Antigone – in the tradition of Hölderlin’s translation and interpretation. This is the arche tamechana, that against which nothing can avail.
In Sophocles’ Antigone, the conflict between Creon and Antigone can be interpreted as a dramatic representation of the tension between the communal, polis-oriented nature of the ancient Greek soul and the rising individualism influenced by the sophists and philosophers of the time. This clash reflects broader cultural and intellectual shifts in ancient Greece during the 5th century BCE, when traditional values were increasingly challenged by new ideas about personal autonomy, justice, and morality.
Creon embodies the ethos of the polis—the city-state as a collective entity that demands loyalty, order, and obedience to maintain social stability. As the newly appointed king of Thebes, he prioritizes the rule of law and the welfare of the state over personal or familial considerations. His decree forbidding the burial of Polyneices, a traitor in his eyes, is rooted in the traditional Greek belief that the polis’s survival depends on unity and the subordination of individual desires to the common good. This reflects the older, Homeric, and archaic Greek soul, where honor and duty to the community were paramount, and the stability of the state was seen as a sacred trust. Creon’s insistence on enforcing his edict, even at the cost of his family, mirrors the polis’s demand for conformity and sacrifice, a value system that predates the philosophical upheavals of Sophocles’ era.
Antigone, by contrast, represents an emergent individualism, influenced by the intellectual currents of the sophists and early philosophers like Socrates, who began questioning traditional authority and emphasizing personal ethics and conscience. Her defiance of Creon’s edict to bury her brother Polyneices stems from a deeply personal sense of justice and piety, rooted in unwritten divine laws rather than human decrees. This stance aligns with the sophists’ challenges to nomos (man-made law) in favor of physis (natural law or individual moral intuition) and anticipates philosophical debates about the autonomy of the individual soul. Antigone’s willingness to die for her principles elevates her personal conviction above the collective will, marking her as a proto-individualist figure who asserts her agency against the state’s authority.
The clash between Creon and Antigone thus externalizes an inner conflict within the Greek psyche during Sophocles’ time: the tension between the communal identity that had long defined Greek society and the growing recognition of individual rights and moral independence. The polis demanded loyalty to its laws and leaders as a means of preserving order after the chaos of civil war (like the one that frames Antigone), yet the sophists and philosophers were sowing seeds of doubt, encouraging people to question whether justice resided solely in the state or within the individual’s reasoning and conscience. Sophocles stages this struggle not as a simple dichotomy but as a tragic collision where both sides possess compelling yet flawed claims, reflecting the complexity of this cultural shift.
Creon’s Driving Forces: Creon is driven by a sense of responsibility to restore order in Thebes after the fratricidal war between Eteocles and Polyneices. His edict is a political act meant to deter treason and reinforce his authority as a new ruler. Fear of Anarchy: He views disobedience—especially from a woman like Antigone—as a threat to the stability of the state. His obsession with control reveals an underlying insecurity about his legitimacy and the fragility of his rule. Pride (Hubris): Creon’s stubbornness and refusal to heed Tiresias, Haemon, or the chorus stem from his pride, a classic tragic flaw. He equates his will with the state’s, unable to separate personal ego from public duty.
Antigone’s Driving Forces, Familial Loyalty and Piety: Antigone is propelled by an unyielding devotion to her brother and the divine laws that mandate burial rites. Her actions honor the traditional Greek value of familial duty, but she interprets it through a personal, uncompromising lens. Moral Conviction: She believes in a higher justice that transcends Creon’s temporal authority, reflecting a proto-philosophical stance that prioritizes eternal principles over contingent laws. Defiance and Identity: Antigone’s resistance is also an assertion of her agency and identity as a woman and a member of the cursed house of Oedipus. Her deathwish-like resolve suggests a complex mix of fatalism and empowerment, as she claims her fate on her own terms.
The Creon-Antigone conflict encapsulates the ancient Greek soul at a crossroads: Creon clings to the polis as the bedrock of meaning and order, while Antigone heralds an individualism that challenges the state’s monopoly on justice. Sophocles does not fully resolve this tension—both characters meet tragic ends, suggesting that neither extreme can prevail without cost. Creon’s communal rigidity collapses under personal loss, and Antigone’s individualism leads to isolation and death. This duality mirrors the unresolved cultural dialogue of Sophocles’ time, as Greece grappled with balancing collective tradition and individual conscience—a tension that would resonate through Western thought for centuries.
The Antigone ode to man says “everywhere journeying, inexperienced and without issue, he comes to nothingness.” Given Creon and Antigone are driven by opposing causes, could this mean our causes animate our lives but really they lead to nothing? A melancholic may see an oppressed person protesting and think “I wish I had a cause.” This is a fundamental tragic truth of human nature.
This interpretation of the “Ode to Man” (from the first stasimon of Antigone, lines 332–375 in the Greek text) and its resonance with Creon and Antigone’s opposing causes taps into a profound and indeed melancholic reading of Sophocles’ tragedy. The line Heidegger translated “everywhere journeying, inexperienced and without issue, he comes to nothingness” (often translated variably, but capturing the same essence)—suggests a fundamental futility in human striving, a theme that aligns with the play’s exploration of purpose, conflict, and mortality.
The “Ode to Man” (often called the “Ode on Man”) is a choral reflection on humanity’s remarkable achievements—mastery over nature, language, thought, and society—juxtaposed with its limits and potential for self-destruction. The phrase “he comes to nothingness” (in some translations, “he comes to naught”) underscores the paradox of human endeavor: for all our ingenuity and passion, our journeys end in oblivion. When applied to Creon and Antigone, this line casts their fiercely opposed causes—Creon’s defense of the polis and Antigone’s devotion to divine law and family—as animating forces that give their lives meaning, yet ultimately lead them to ruin.
Creon’s Cause: Creon’s commitment to state authority drives his every action, lending his life a rigid structure and purpose. He journeys “everywhere” in the sense of navigating the political landscape, imposing order on chaos. Yet, his inexperience—his inability to adapt or heed warnings—leads him to “nothingness”: the loss of his son Haemon, wife Eurydice, and moral credibility. His cause, though it animates his rule, collapses into personal and communal desolation.
Antigone’s Cause: Antigone’s defiance is her life’s animating spark, a journey of moral conviction that sets her apart. Her “inexperience” lies in her refusal to compromise with practical realities, and “without issue” could hint at her literal childlessness or her isolation from the living community. Her cause leads her to the tomb, a literal “nothingness” where her voice and agency are extinguished.
In this light, the ode suggests that causes—however noble or necessary—propel us forward but cannot escape the human condition’s endpoint: death and dissolution. Creon and Antigone’s opposing drives highlight this paradox: their lives are defined by their struggles, yet those struggles deliver them to the same tragic “nothingness.”
The melancholic observer—“I wish I had a cause”—captures a fundamental tragic truth about human nature: we crave purpose to animate our existence, yet those very purposes may be illusory or self-defeating. The oppressed person protesting embodies this duality: their cause gives them vitality, a reason to resist, yet the melancholic sees the potential futility, the “nothingness” of the most passionate struggle. This aligns with Sophocles’ worldview, where human greatness (deinotēs, often translated as “wonder” or “terrible power” in the ode) is inseparable from suffering and loss.
Causes, whether communal (Creon) or individual (Antigone), are what make us human. They give shape to our “journeying,” filling the void of existence with meaning. A melancholic might envy this, seeing their own lack of purpose as a kind of living death. These causes “really lead to nothing.” Creon’s order crumbles, Antigone’s piety ends in silence, and the polis endures only through others’ suffering. The ode’s melancholic undertone implies that all human effort—however grand—circles back to mortality and insignificance.
This reading positions Antigone as a meditation on the bittersweet necessity of causes. They are the fire that keeps us alive, driving us to act, resist, or build, yet they cannot save us from the “nothingness” that awaits. The melancholic’s longing reflects a universal ache: we need causes to feel human, but their ultimate futility reveals our fragility. Sophocles, writing in an era of war and philosophical upheaval, seems to ask whether this tension—between purpose and pointlessness—is the essence of tragedy. Creon and Antigone, locked in their fatal dance, embody this truth: their causes make them larger than life, yet reduce them to dust.
In short, the ode can indeed suggest that our causes animate us only to lead us to nothing, a melancholic insight that cuts to the core of human nature. It’s a tragic irony that the very things that define us also undo us, leaving the observer both inspired and despairing.
The line “manifold are the wonders, but nothing more wondrous than man” (from the “Ode to Man” in Antigone, typically translated from the Greek “πολλὰ τὰ δεινὰ κουδὲν ἀνθρώπου δεινότερον πέλει”) might carry a sarcastic edge in the context of the Oedipus family’s tragedy. While sarcasm in the modern, biting sense might not fully align with the tone of Sophocles’ choral odes, the line can certainly be read with a heavy dose of irony—especially given the catastrophic backdrop of Antigone. Let’s explore this possibility.
The “Ode to Man” (lines 332–375) opens with this famous declaration: humanity is the most deinos (wondrous, terrible, awe-inspiring) thing in existence. The chorus goes on to celebrate man’s achievements—taming the sea, mastering the earth, harnessing animals, developing language and thought, and building societies. At face value, it’s a hymn to human ingenuity and resilience. But this praise is sung in the midst of a play where human actions—specifically those of the Oedipus family—unravel into chaos, death, and despair. The ode follows Antigone’s arrest for defying Creon and precedes her confrontation with him, setting the stage for the spiraling tragedy that engulfs her, Creon, and their kin.
Given this context, the assertion that “nothing is more wondrous than man” takes on a double-edged quality. The Greek term deinos itself is ambiguous: it can mean “wonderful” in a positive sense or “terrible” in a foreboding one. Sophocles likely exploits this ambiguity, and the Oedipus family’s fate—cursed by hubris, defiance, and unrelenting doom—casts a shadow over the ode’s apparent optimism.
While “sarcasm” today often implies a mocking or scornful tone, the ancient Greek chorus typically adopts a more reflective or didactic stance. A sarcastic reading in the modern sense (e.g., a snarky “Oh, sure, man’s so impressive”) might overstate the chorus’s intent. However, a deeply ironic interpretation fits perfectly. Irony—where the surface meaning contrasts sharply with an underlying truth—was a hallmark of Sophoclean tragedy. Here, the chorus might seem to praise man’s greatness while implicitly acknowledging the horrific consequences of that same “wondrous” nature, as exemplified by the house of Oedipus.
Oedipus himself was deinos—brilliant in solving the Sphinx’s riddle, yet terrible in his unwitting crimes of patricide and incest. His children inherit this duality: Antigone’s courage is wondrous, but it leads to her death; Creon’s authority is impressive, but it destroys his family. The “wonders” of man, in this lineage, are inseparable from self-inflicted ruin.
By the time the chorus sings this ode, the audience knows the family’s history and senses the impending disaster. Praising man’s triumphs feels hollow—or at least bittersweet—when those triumphs coexist with such profound failure. The ode’s list of achievements (e.g., conquering nature) contrasts starkly with man’s inability to conquer fate or inner flaws, as seen in Creon’s hubris and Antigone’s fatal resolve.
If we lean into this ironic reading, “nothing more wondrous than man” could be Sophocles’ way of highlighting the paradox of humanity: we are extraordinary in our capacities yet equally extraordinary in our capacity for destruction. The Oedipus family amplifies this to an extreme—Oedipus’ intellect, Antigone’s piety, Creon’s leadership—all “wondrous” traits that precipitate “nothingness,” as the ode later notes. The chorus, as the voice of Theban elders, might not be openly mocking, but their words carry a knowing weight: man’s wonders are real, yet they often lead to tragedy, not triumph.
Our earlier point about causes animating life only to end in nothingness reinforces this. The ode’s opening line could be a wry nod to that truth: yes, man is wondrous—look at how passionately Antigone and Creon pursue their causes—but look also at where it gets them. The sarcasm, if we call it that, lies in the gap between the chorus’s lofty praise and the grim reality unfolding on stage.
It drips with tragic irony that borders on the sardonic. Against the backdrop of the Oedipus family’s relentless downfall, “nothing more wondrous than man” reads less as a straightforward celebration and more as a poignant, even cutting, reflection on human potential entwined with human doom. Sophocles invites us to marvel at man’s greatness while quietly reminding us of its cost—a subtlety that makes the ode, and the play, enduringly haunting.